Thursday 28th of November 2024

baseball won’t be played anymore?....

A bold, provocative reckoning with our current political delusions and dysfunctions.

Ever since its publication in 1651, Thomas Hobbes's Leviathan has unsettled and challenged how we understand the world. Condemned and vilified by each new generation, his cold political vision continues to see through any number of human political and ethical vanities.

The New Leviathans: Thoughts after Liberalism
by John Gray

 

In his wonderfully stimulating book The New Leviathans, John Gray allows us to understand the world of the 2020s with all its contradictions, moral horrors, and disappointments. The collapse of the USSR ushered in an era of near apoplectic triumphalism in the West: a genuine belief that a rational, liberal, well-managed future now awaited humankind and that tyranny, nationalism, and unreason lay in the past. Since then, so many terrible events have occurred and so many poisonous ideas have flourished, and yet our liberal certainties treat them as aberrations that will somehow dissolve. Hobbes would not be so confident.

Filled with fascinating and challenging observations, The New Leviathans is a powerful meditation on historical and current folly. As a species we always seem to be struggling to face the reality of base and delusive human instincts. Might a more self-aware, realistic, and disabused ethics help us?

 

SO, WHAT IS THE PROBLEM? THE MISES INSTITUTE — THE FREE MARKETEER INSTITUTE FROM “AUSTRIA” — LETS US HAVE A DIFFERENT OPINION THROUGH AN ANALYSIS BY DAVID GORDON:

John Gray is a strange case. He is a political philosopher who taught for many decades at Oxford and the London School of Economics, and he has become one of the leading British “public intellectuals.” A friend of the rich and famous, including George Soros, he abandoned long ago the classical liberal beliefs he held in the late 1970s and early 1980s. By no means, though, has he turned into a conventional leftist. He realizes that a powerful state is dangerous and warns against utopian projects that purport to make the world a better place by bringing people under control. This realization has not led him to embrace the free market, as he did in his youth. Why not? This is the topic I’d like to address in this week’s column, and I’ll suggest the answer lies in some very bad arguments he offers.

First, though, is the insightful realization. He compares the states of the contemporary world powers to Thomas Hobbes’s Leviathan. Hobbes argued that a strong state was needed to prevent people enflamed by religious passions from igniting civil war, as he believed had occurred in Britain in the 1640s, but the “goals of Hobbes’s Leviathan were strictly limited. Beyond securing its subjects against one another and external enemies, it had no remit.”

The contemporary state, though often less absolute in its powers than in Leviathan, attempts to do more than secure its subjects, and this has often led to disaster:

The purposes of the new Leviathans are more far-reaching. In a time when the future seems profoundly uncertain, they aim to secure meaning in life for their subjects. Like the totalitarian regimes of the twentieth century, the new Leviathans are engineers of souls.

The upshot has been the return of the state of nature in artificial forms. Even as they promise safety, the new regimes foster insecurity. . . . Within Western society, rival groups seek to capture the power of the state in a new war of all against all between self-defined collective entities. There is an unrelenting struggle for the control of thought and language. Enclaves of freedom persist, but a liberal situation based on the practice of tolerance has passed into history.

In schools and universities, education inculcates conformity with the ruling progressive ideology. The arts are judged by whether they serve approved political goals. Dissidents from orthodoxy on race, gender and empire find their careers terminated and their public lives erased.

 

You might imagine that the solution to these problems is in essence simple. If the contemporary state is dangerous, why not radically reduce its power or, better yet, do away with it altogether? Can’t people attain a peaceful and prosperous society through social cooperation in the free market? So Ludwig von Mises and Murray Rothbard have taught us, but Gray does not agree with them.

He deploys two main arguments against the free market. The first of these arguments is that support for the free market stems from individualist premises that he thinks are mistaken. These assumptions come from Hobbes, whom Gray considers the first liberal despite his support for a state with absolute power. Hobbes, Gray says, thought that “human nature is universal in its needs; divergent cultural identities are superficial and insignificant. With the application of reason, government can be improved. Human beings can overcome their conflicts, and learn to live in peace.”

Gray counters that these assumptions are half-truths:

People regularly give up peace and security in order to defend a form of life they believe to be superior to others. The most basic human goods may be universal, but they are often sacrificed in order to fight for values that are specific to particular ways of living. Society and government can be improved, but what is gained can always be lost.

 

The basic mistake in Gray’s line of thought is that he views the case for the free market as a historical prophecy. Classical liberals are supposed to hold that people will overcome their irrational passions and recognize that reason requires the free market. This is a belief he takes to be part of the “Enlightenment project,” a phrase from Alasdair MacIntyre that Gray often uses in his books, though not in this one. (The words used to drive my late friend Ralph Raico to distraction. Raico once cornered Gray at a Liberty Fund conference and demanded that Gray reveal the location of the “project.”)

What Gray fails to see is that although some classical liberals were optimistic about the success of their ideas, the argument for the free market is prudential and ethical, not historical. The argument has two steps: if you want peace and prosperity, you should establish and maintain a free market, and you should want peace and prosperity. The claim that people will see the force of these considerations and act as they mandate is by comparison of secondary significance. It is quite possible to be a classical liberal and also to think that people are too evil and stupid to realize that the free market is desirable. H. L. Mencken and Albert Jay Nock come to mind as examples of such classical liberals.

I’m afraid it gets worse when we get to Gray’s second main argument against the free market. He focuses on Friedrich Hayek, whom he takes to be offering a Darwinian argument: Hayek, “one of the most influential late twentieth-century ideologues, believed that market capitalism spread through an evolutionary process. The most productive system was the free market, which would win out in Darwinian fashion over all others.” In arguing in this way, Hayek “departs from the most important discovery in modern science. As understood by Charles Darwin, evolution has no destination. Humankind is not the endpoint of natural selection, which may well result in its extinction.”

Gray has made a silly mistake. The claim that an economic system will supplant others in competition does not imply that biological evolution has a goal or that human beings will never die out. If someone argues that very fast baseball players have a competitive advantage over slow players, he is not refuted by the likelihood that at some future time, baseball won’t be played anymore.

https://mises.org/mises-wire/shades-gray

GUSTOPIAN:

HERE WE GO AGAIN: Can’t people attain a peaceful and prosperous society through social cooperation in the free market? So Ludwig von Mises and Murray Rothbard have taught us, but Gray does not agree with them.

THIS IS BELIEVING IN THE FAIRIES. THIS EXPECT THAT IN ANY POPULATION, THAT ALL THE PEOPLE ARE HONEST AND GENUINE… THIS IS FAR FROM REALITY. 

THERE ARE ROBBERS, PSYCHOPATHS, SOCIOPATHS, MURDERERS, NUTCASES, PEOPLE WHO DO NOT WANT TO PLAY BY THE RULES, SNEAKS, RULERS AND SLAVES, IDEOLOGISTS, RELIGIOUS INFLUENCE-OLOGISTS, EXTREMISTS, OLD KOOKS, YOUNG LOONIES HOMOS, HETEROS, PHOBOS, POKER DEALERS AND USED-CAR SALESMEN — TO SUCH A GREAT EXTEND — THAT WE’RE ALL CROOKS. 

SUCH A GROUP (THE WHITE MEN — BECAUSE THIS MISES IS A WHITE MAN IDEA — AND HAS NO CONSIDERATIONS FOR DIFFERENT ETHNIC WAY TO DEAL) IS IMPOSSIBLE TO RULE WITHOUT A SEAT OF DECISION MAKING. AND IT’S NOT SIMPLE. IT’S SHIFTY, DEPENDING OF THE GROUP THAT CONTROL THE DECISIONS… SO WHO? HOW? 

BASEBALL WON’T BE PLAYED ANYMORE? BASEBALL IS PLAYED IN THE AMERICAN EMPIRE BY AMERICANS AND THEIR CRONIES — AND US TROOPS.

The top five countries with the highest number of stationed US troops are Japan (53,246), Germany (35,188), South Korea (24,159), Italy (12,405), and the United Kingdom (9,949). These troops are stationed at US-owned and operated military bases.

THE FRENCH STILL RESENT THAT THEY HAVEN’T INVENTED A SPORT WORTH MENTIONING… THAT’S WHY A FRENCHMAN REINVENTED THE OLYMPICS WHICH IS SUPPOSED TO BE A-POLITICAL, BUT HEY… AND IF ATHLETES ARE NOT DOPED TO THE EYEBALLS, THEIR SHOES NEET TO BE CERTIFIED BECAUSE OF THE SPRINGNESS OF THE SOLES. IT WOULD BE BETTER IF EVERY ATHLETES WAS DOING THEIR STUFF NAKED TO AVOID CHEATING.… 

 

FREE JULIAN ASSANGE NOW....

 

CARTOON AT TOP FROM PUNCH MELBOURNE 1888... THIEF TRIPS A SENSOR, LIGHT COMES ON, CAMERA TAKES A PICTURE AND THE PHONE IS CONNECTED TO THE POLICE AUTOMATICALLY...

malignant....

by Amar Djerrad 

The world is going through a pivotal period which is characterized by a shift from a criminal, predatory, subjugating world which only lasts through force, compromises, blackmail and wars, towards a world wanting to be fairer and more balanced! Let's be honest! Asians, Africans and Latin Americans (in part) know that this reversal is beneficial for them! This evolution, favored by scientific progress, can only bring balance and harmony.

A 2nd antagonistic pole, for balance or “new imperialism”? 

The 21st century will see the world split into two antagonistic poles where the West can only lose! It is a natural and irreversible historical process, resulting from the evolution of human behavior, its contradictions, ambitions, interests, whims and its villainous actions. Deliberate attempts to divert this course, in order to perpetuate their undue privileges, will be in vain!  

Imperialism and colonialism arise from a human quirk characterized by pride, greed and perversity; deficiencies that alter the vision of the world in all its complexity. After the disappearance of serfdom and slavery, and while vestiges of colonialism persist, we are today confronted with other forms of thought and action such as neocolonialism and the "supremacist and globalist world", which are reaching their inevitable end, despite attempts to deviate from their course! 

The groupings of States/nations within the framework of common and existential defenses represent an additional force which can prevent any hegemonic intention through aggressions which become improbable when the provocateur urges responses risking causing unbearable damage. “Tyrants are only great because we are on our knees". (La Boétie). It is true that it is not necessary to destroy this "world", although it is possible. It is simpler to no longer allow him to illegally appropriate anything and to remove all plundering tendencies, so that everyone can live according to their means and abilities, in harmony and balanced exchange, without feeling the need to covetously covet the possessions of others. 

Since the fall of the Soviet Union, we have witnessed a drift towards a “globalist”, “supremacist” spirit, while a large part of the world is in another perspective! They do not see that in the wisdom of Confucius “Arrogance goes before ruin, pride goes before a fall". We are there in view of what is happening in the Middle East with Israeli colonialism, in Ukraine against Russia, in Taiwan against China, in Africa to get rid of neocolonialism, etc. Westerners have never acted for good and truth. They even mock their people by depriving them of the opportunity to see the hidden reality that provides a semblance of peace that lasts only for the duration of a rose. “In the calmest rivers, devils swarm» says a Russian proverb! Their demon has come out to find itself confronted with a quiet, irreducible and unshakeable force! 

A new “imperialism”? It is better that one which we do not know, but which gives concrete indications to the contrary than that which has been “experienced” for centuries and which has ruined them! Did the Russians and Chinese ever colonize and exploit a single country in Africa – unlike the West which has a disastrous, barbaric colonial past by colonizing it in its entirety, the majority of which by France – to accuse them of colonialist aims in this continent?

NATO locks itself in Ukraine against a crushing Russia

It is clear that the Atlanticists have been waging a war against Russia since February 24, 2022, without formally declaring it, using Ukraine as a proxy as well as mercenaries, while inflicting unprecedented sanctions which have dangerously turned against them! You need to have the intelligence of the Russians to achieve the feat of reversing difficult situations! 

We hear them incessantly and deliriously repeating contradictory remarks on Russian and Chinese threats, their “unhealthy” objectives, their power or impotence, warning that we must not “push Russia into the arms of China” while They are together in the BRIC, all in a nauseating hodgepodge reflecting their dismay. If they are capable of this, why then resort to a proxy war that needlessly destroyed Ukraine and caused significant losses in its army without directly and loyally engaging their own troops? Why surreptitiously encourage the split of Taiwan when they fully recognize China's sovereignty over the island? This is a form of American-style bluffing and intimidation followed by gullible European nations! They are trying to achieve through propaganda and lies what they failed to achieve through military means. 

The Baltic countries, Poland, Finland, Sweden, the Czech Republic, Romania, France, the United Kingdom and Germany among others seem reluctant to openly engage in an armed conflict against Russia in view of declarations tinged with uncertainty hidden behind a semblance of bravery. “Courage, let’s run away!” The United States, appearing to be the main beneficiaries of the conflict in Ukraine to the detriment of Europe, has ruled out any “official” sending of its troops without denying their “support”. The idea of ​​bringing down Russia or China is more of a chimera born from a feeling of frustration and fantasy among those who have lost their free will. 

The American-Anglo-Franco-Zionists are like this criminal brandishing a knife in front of someone and asking them to only react if they are hit! We don't play this roulette with the Russians! Knife, divisions or nuclear weapons, here is an overview of the possible responses mentioned by Putin: “… We remember the fate of those who once sent their contingents to the territory of our country. Today the consequences... will be much more tragic... you won't even have time to blink when Article 5 is executed", or "they have been accustomed for centuries to filling their bellies with human flesh and their pockets with money... they must understand that the vampire ball is coming to an end»1 or again, to the question of an American journalist on the possibility of a first nuclear strike on Russia, the response of the Russian president was unequivocal: “they won't have time to regret it». 

We therefore believe that the use of nuclear power in the American narrative remains a form of intimidation, a bluff. Their system, built on predation and the money of a few dozen multi-billionaires, will not allow them to venture into such an enterprise.

The trap of arrogance: “He who thinks he catches is caught” 

What is remarkable is that history often has surprises in store for malicious individuals, boasters and liars. The imperialist West finds itself caught in the traps it constantly sets for others. All institutions and organizations (especially financial) established mainly after the Second World War to promote democracy, freedoms and human rights, by imposing their will on others through the abusive use of information technology. advanced information, have proven to be tools of provocation and domination aimed at coercing, or even overthrowing, governments that do not follow their globalist ideology. They finally turned against them in a deplorable way! The Internet has proven to be a particularly effective means of thwarting them to the point of shaking their system of governance, security and “information”! 

These “social” media have surpassed their traditional media of propaganda and subversion! “He is taken who thought he was taking !” In seeking to manipulate and deceive, they ended up being caught in the same global subversive net that they spun for others. 

Among these manipulations are those consisting of ignoring the start dates of conflicts as well as their historical context in order to mislead about the objectives. Which explains the blocking of free debates which are only allowed within the framework of a pre-established communicative narrative, but which now seem to be collapsing! Hence the sudden turn for another more diverse one like “stop the Russians from winning". Funny goal!

Europe lowered, under the caudine forks of the USA 

A Europe that fell very low under the clutches of the USA thanks to the “assistance” provided at the end of the Second World War which was transformed into the “right of intervention”. Here they are in a sort of 'bis repetita' which pushes them towards self-destruction with a view to a reconstruction market which begins with the relocation of their industries made uncompetitive due to a ban on the purchase of Russian energy . In this regard, the latest independent investigation, by data analysis, of a certain «Mortymer”, demonstrated that the sabotage of the Nord Stream2 is the work of the Anglo-Americans involving English personalities, confirming the assertions of Seymour Hersh and the Russian services. 

Not satisfied with the consequences for Russia and insensitive to failure, the European oligarchs have pushed their dirty maneuver to the point of wanting to use the interest generated by Russian assets to finance Ukraine, according to them. In fact, it is a manipulation aimed, certainly, at raising money for Ukraine, but above all at redirecting most of it towards Israel, their latest puppet; without imagining the astonishing Russian responses! “He who swallows a whole coconut trusts his anus» says an Ivorian proverb. Which doesn't seem feasible! 

They nevertheless remain quick to show off their pectorals against small countries... “Small” African countries which have succeeded in ousting powers such as France and the United States from their territory by establishing, henceforth, sovereignly, relations with whom they want and when they want! Let's see what Nathalie says about it.3 

This is to emphasize that arrogance corrupts minds to the point of alienation! “For some, arrogance takes the place of greatness; the inhumanity of firmness; and deceitfulness, of mind» (Jacques Sternberg).

In conclusion, it appears that getting rid of their imperialism and colonialism; guarantee respect for the rights of peoples, including those of the Palestinians; withdrawing their threatening military bases around the world and establishing balanced relations with countries, do not figure in their vision. They remain locked in their paradoxes and contradictions, only noticing their failures once their actions are accomplished, without recognizing them; then they start again. They hear nothing of the advice of the Sages.

They are aware of their loss of global influence, but only manage to find "solutions" through behaviors that fuel anti-Westernism, thus accelerating their decline and leading to the countries of the European Union who do not even perceive that “Brexit”, for example, is nothing more than a ploy for the UK to avoid the repercussions of US policy on the EU.

The model of Western “democracy” which marginalizes patriotism and the interests of people, including their own, favoring groups of influence organized around oligarchs is the harbinger of decline.

Thus, they seem to reach the final phase of an irreversible process in their historical evolution, as experienced by all the disappeared empires.

There remains this malignant tumor in the Middle East called Israel (supported in particular by the Rothschilds) with its disastrous and satanic colonial projects. This entity believes it can progress happily against the tide of the historical evolution of the world while ignoring the people who observe their malicious actions, from a bygone era, towards the Palestinians. An anachronism that offends intelligence and reason!

https://en.reseauinternational.net/limperialisme-occidental-en-declin-face-a-limperialisme-bienseant-des-brics-en-formation/

 

 

READ FROM TOP

 

FREE JULIAN ASSANGE NOW....

being nobody....

 

Why the Left should reject Heidegger’s thought. (Part 1: The Question of Being)Originally published: Midwestern Marx by Colin Bodayle

 

Heideggerian thought is everywhere. A list of thinkers influenced by Heidegger reads like a “who’s who” of famous twentieth century philosophers. Foucault said: “For me, Heidegger has always been the essential philosopher.”1 Derrida once called Heidegger “the great unavoidable thinker of the century.”2 Sartre conceived of Being and Nothingness while reading Heidegger’s “What is Metaphysics?” Deleuze acknowledges the influence of Heidegger in the Preface to Difference and Repetition.3 Žižek wrote his first book on Heidegger.4 Many of Heidegger’s students became famous philosophers, including several who significantly impacted political theory: Hannah Arendt would develop the discourse of “totalitarianism” found in liberal philosophy, Leo Strauss would influence the neoconservative movement, and Herbert Marcuse would be a leading thinker for the New Left. It seems surprising that Heidegger should exert this much influence on contemporary thought, given that he was an unapologetic Nazi who began each lecture with “Heil Hitler” during his tenure as rector of Freiburg. One wonders, especially, why he has been embraced by so many thinkers on the Left.

Heidegger scholars have long attempted to separate Heidegger’s philosophy from his Nazism. This separation became increasingly difficult, however, after the Black Notebooks were published in 2014. These personal notebooks offer further evidence of Heidegger’s open embrace of racism, antisemitism, and Nazism. They also show Heidegger developing some of his most famous philosophical concepts directly out of Nazi ideology. In 1933, Heidegger writes:

The Führer has awakened a new actuality, giving our thinking the correct course and impetus. Otherwise, despite all the thoroughness, it would have remained lost in itself and would only with great difficulty have found its way to effectiveness.5

When Heidegger’s collected works were published, evidence of the extent of Heidegger’s Nazi involvement was largely erased. As Richard Wolin points out: “Following the war, Heidegger fabricated and rewrote entire passages, inserting them in earlier texts in order to promote the myth that, during the 1930’s, he had acted ‘heroically,’ as an intellectual and political dissident.”6 Among those “in the know,” however, it was already an open secret that many of Heidegger’s published works had been altered to hide incriminating references to Hitler, fascism, or “world-Judaism.”7

While most leftists have no problem rejecting Heidegger as a person, many ostensibly progressive or left-wing philosophers have nevertheless adopted Heideggerian positions. This includes thinkers who identify as communists like Sartre, Kojève, and Marcuse. There are reasons for Heidegger’s popularity. Heidegger talks about feelings of angst, the struggle to be authentic amid conformity, the weight of future possibilities, and our fears regarding our inevitable mortality. Young people are drawn to Heidegger because they wrestle with these questions, especially given the pressures of capitalist society. As a young person, I too was drawn to Being and Time for similar reasons, leading me to spend almost a decade studying Heidegger’s thought. Although I have broken completely with Heidegger, I wouldn’t deny that Being and Time is a powerful and thought-provoking work of philosophy. Yet there are deep-seated problems within Heidegger’s thinking, contradictions that bubble to the surface when we examine Heidegger’s positions carefully. Criticizing Heidegger is important. Seeds of Heideggerianism are scattered throughout leftist thought, and we cannot simply point to Heidegger’s Nazi roots to unplant them. We must scorch the soil of Heidegger’s thinking with the fires of critique.

Heidegger writes in idiosyncratic jargon, coining a cryptic vocabulary of neologisms based on the etymology of German words. The task of translating Heidegger is a nightmare. Often, his language puts a spell over his audience, warding Heidegger from hasty criticisms. Demystifying Heideggerese takes a great deal of effort, so I have decided to divide this task into a series of articles, touching on some of the main points of relevance in each. My aim in this series is to clarify why Marxists should reject Heideggerian thinking. In the current article, I will be focusing on the most significant aspect of Heidegger’s thought: the question of being. In the next article, I will be exploring his analysis of Dasein in Being and Time. In the final article, I will be examining his critique of technology and modern science.

Heidegger’s Single Thought: The Ontological Difference

Heidegger once claimed that “Each thinker only thinks one single thought.”8 The great philosophers, Heidegger claimed, take one idea and paint all of reality in its colors. If Heidegger had “one thought,” this would be the ontological difference. The ontological difference is the distinction between beings (things that are) and being (their “to be”). According to Heidegger, philosophers have overlooked this distinction. Whenever philosophers have asked about the meaning of being, they have treated being as if it were a being. Philosophy has failed to consider “being itself,” that is, being apart from beings.

The history of Western metaphysics, according to Heidegger, consists of various attempts to explain being through the lens of beings. The Presocratic philosopher Thales, for example, claimed that being was water, interpreting the being of beings in general in terms of a specific kind of being. For Thales, solid objects are frozen liquid, air is just vaporous water, and fire is akin to steam. The being of every being, for Thales, is water. Beginning with Aristotle, Heidegger claims, metaphysics adopts a twofold strategy for explaining the being of beings. First, it uses the being of some special being to explain being in general, then it grounds the existence of all beings in terms of some highest being. For Aristotle, for example, being is understood in terms of motion and this account is grounded in the unmoved mover. Heidegger calls these kinds of explanations “ontotheology” because they begin with an ontology of being in general and then ground this ontology in a theology of the highest being. In the Middle Ages, Heidegger claims, we enter into a new epoch of the history of being. For the Medievals, beings in general are understood as created out of nothing, and the totality of beings are grounded in God, the highest being. Beginning with Descartes, however, philosophy moves away from God and towards the human mind. Now, beings are understood as representations grounded in the human mind or transcendental ego. This modern conception of beings, in fact, somewhat resembles what Marxists would understand by the term “idealism.” The final epoch in the history of being, according to Heidegger, is modern technology, which corresponds to Hegelian philosophy as the complete system of science and the two “inversions” of Hegelianism: Nietzscheanism and Marxism. In modernity, everything becomes an object for technological manipulation with modern science revealing how we can dominate and control nature. The center of this final epoch of ontotheology, according to Heidegger, is the isolated, finite human will, a will that simply wants to keep on willing, subordinating everything to its desire for control and mastery, including the human species itself. Heidegger argues that philosophy and the history of metaphysics ends with the technological interpretation of the meaning of being, covering over the ontological difference and making it impossible for any new philosophical paradigm to emerge.

For both Heidegger and Bill Clinton everything depends on “what is is.” Each epoch of metaphysics, Heidegger claims, operates under a specific interpretation of the meaning of being in general. Yet each epoch also covers over the difference between being and beings. Yet what is the difference between being and beings? We might illustrate this using the example of light. If I turn on the lights in the room, the objects become visible through the light. The objects in the room, however, are not the light itself. The lightbulb, too, is not the light, but the source of the light. In fact, the lightbulb is also made visible by the light. The light itself, however, cannot be made visible by means of light. Instead, we notice that there is light because the objects themselves become visible. The relationship between being and beings, for Heidegger, is similar to the relationship between visible objects and light. We cannot illuminate being by treating it as a being, because being is the “to be” of beings. Being itself is not a being, which means that, strictly speaking, being “is not.” Heidegger thus calls being the presencing of presence, the manifestness of the manifest. He also describes being using contradictory, almost dialectical-sounding language, saying that being is “revealing/concealing.” Just like the light reveals itself by revealing bright objects, but light cannot directly reveal light, being reveals itself by revealing beings yet concealing itself.

The unconcealment of being makes metaphysics possible. Metaphysics and modern science, however, distort this more primordial unconcealment by representing being in various ways. Science, for example, represents beings in terms of their mathematically quantifiable and manipulatable properties. Heidegger claims that this distorts a more primordial unconcealment of being. For Heidegger, we discover being itself in the sheer “thatness,” the fact that something is rather than is not. We discover such unconcealment, Heidegger thinks, whenever we let something be without trying to represent it. Art and poetry accomplish this feat. A painting of a river, for Heidegger, simply aims to present the being of the river, not to quantify the river or measure its force. He writes: “The more essential the work [of art] opens itself, the more luminous becomes the uniqueness of the fact that it is rather than is not.”9 A work of art, by putting its subject matter on display, lets it appear as itself. We are overwhelmed by its strangeness. “Only when the strangeness of beings oppresses us does it arouse and evoke wonder.”10 Being, for Heidegger, is the realization that “holy shit, there are things!” This pure givenness, the fact that anything exists at all, this “unconcealment” or “manifestness” is what Heidegger identifies with being as such.

The Contradictions of Heideggerian Thought

Heidegger follows Hegel in recognizing that being is not a being. Yet Hegel draws the conclusion that pure being is empty indeterminacy, a total abstraction, the negation of all determinacy and content. Being, in other words, is nothing. In fact, this is the first dialectical transformation of Hegel’s Logic, the thought of pure being turning into its opposite. Heidegger cannot accept this conclusion. He attempts to avoid this dialectic by making the following argument: The question “What is being?” seems paradoxical, because in asking “what isbeing?”, we presuppose that we already understand the “is.” Yet we do understand the question, Heidegger says, we just can’t articulate the meaning of “being.” Heidegger thus concludes we implicitly understand the meaning of being, and that we always operate with an implicit understanding of the meaning of being. This understanding of being determines the basis upon which anything can appear or be understood at all. For something to appear, Heidegger claims, it must appear as something, and this requires an understanding of what it means for something to be. From this, Heidegger concludes that we cannot speak of being apart from our understanding of being. In his later language, being is the unconcealment of beings, yet this unconcealment only takes place within the sphere of human existence. Even Heidegger’s term for human beings, Da-sein (literally “being-there”) indicates this, since as Heidegger says, Dasein is “the site that being necessitates for its opening up,” that is, the site where being unconceals itself.11

Does this mean that Heidegger is not really concerned with what actually exists in the real world, but only with the appearance or phenomenon of being? Put differently, is he talking about how we understand being or reality, or about being or reality itself? This question produced a lively debate between the Heidegger scholars Thomas Sheehan and Richard Capobianco.12 This scholarly quarrel, however, is merely a manifestation of a deeper contradiction within Heidegger’s own thinking. Heidegger claims that if Dasein no longer exists, then we cannot speak of “being.” Heidegger writes: “Being (not beings) is dependent upon the understanding of being, that is, reality (not the real) is dependent upon care” (SZ, 212).13 By this, Heidegger means that “being” belongs to our implicit or explicit understanding of the being of beings. Human beings, moreover, are finite and temporal, which makes the understanding of being also finite and temporal. Heidegger struggles throughout his entire career to express this point. Consider what Heidegger is saying: “Being (not beings) is dependent upon the understanding of being.” He puts the phrase “(not beings)” in parentheses, yet this implies the statement: “beings are not dependent upon the understanding of being,” or put positively: “beings are independent of the understanding of being.” Yet this statement cannot be correct, since it says: “beings are,” which would seem to be a statement about the being of beings. Heidegger wants to say that the things in the world are independently of the human understanding of being, but they have no being (are not) unless they appear to human beings. These two things cannot both be true. Lukács rightly calls this “epistemological hocus-pocus.”14 From this passage, Thomas Sheehan draws the conclusion that for Heidegger: “Before homo sapiens evolved, there was no ‘being’ on earth… because ‘being’ for Heidegger does not mean ‘in existence.’”15 When Sheehan says “existence,” however, he cannot mean this in any Heideggerian sense of the word, because Heidegger knows no sense of being or existence outside of Dasein’s understanding of being. Nevertheless, Heidegger himself is frequently forced to speak in this contradictory manner about being. He even starts crossing out the word “is” when talking about being.

Heidegger’s Subjective Idealism

If a tree falls in the forest, does it make a sound? For materialists, the answer is simple: Of course it does. Sound is a vibration of the air, and the tree landing makes the air vibrate regardless of whether anyone hears it. For idealist philosophers, however, the question is far more complicated. An objective idealist (say, Husserl) would claim that it does make a sound, since if a person were present, they would hear it. No one actually hears the sound, but it would be possible for a mind to hear it. Heidegger takes a far more extreme position than the objective idealists. For Heidegger, the being of the sound depends on Dasein, and we can only speak of its mind-independence if we have already presupposed human beings with an understanding of the meaning of being.

Being, for Heidegger, only appears within the horizon of human finitude and history. He thus writes:
Before Newton’s laws were discovered, they were not “true.” From this it does not follow that they were false or even that they would become false if ontically no discoveredness was possible any longer … The fact that before Newton they were neither true nor false cannot mean that the beings which they point out in a discovering way did not previously exist. These laws became true through Newton, through them beings in themselves became accessible for Dasein (SZ, 226-27).16
Heidegger does not deny the truth of Newton’s laws, yet he claims that we cannot speak of the truth or falsity of these laws until they were discovered by Newton. Beings must be accessible for us before we can speak of their being. Heidegger thus wraps objective truth inside subjective idealism.

Normally, we think of truth as the correspondence between a thought or statement and reality. Heidegger claims, however, that truth as “correspondence” depends on the discoveryof truth. We cannot check to see whether an idea corresponds to reality unless we have already discovered reality. Yet only human beings can discover reality, and these discoveries can be lost or forgotten. Heidegger thus says: “The fact that there are ‘eternal truths’ will not be adequately proven until it is successfully demonstrated that Dasein has been and will be for all eternity” (SZ, 227). Heidegger claims there are no eternal truths because if human beings go extinct, all knowledge is lost and so nothing is true. Being and truth die with Dasein. The laws of physics are no longer true if human beings cease to exist.

Heidegger’s history of being and critique of Western metaphysics rests on this basic contradiction within his philosophy. For Heidegger, human history is a series of epochs, each with its own interpretation of the history of being. We cannot escape the horizon of human finitude. Yet because Heidegger eschews the language of consciousness and mind for Dasein, he claims to be speaking of “mind-independent beings.” Beings, he claims, are mind-independent, but their being is Dasein dependent. No Dasein, no being.

Heidegger recognizes that knowledge production is a historical process, one that requires intellectual labor, scientific experiments, and institutions that transmit and preserve this knowledge. On this point, Heidegger is quite correct. Yet the truth or falsity of knowledge does not depend on knowledge production. Truth or falsity is independent of discovery, and beings are whether human beings exist or not. They do not require human beings to be. Heidegger claims to be beyond the subjective and the objective, yet he merely collapses both into the subjectivity of human finitude and history. This Heideggerian framework leads to absurd claims. Consider, for example, the French anthropologist-philosopher Bruno Latour, who claimed that Pharaoh Ramses II didn’t die of tuberculosis because the bacteria wasn’t discovered until 1882. Heidegger does not “solve” the problem of the relationship between mind and world—he collapses all objectivity into finite human subjectivity.

Marxist philosophy cannot ally itself with Heideggerian subjective idealism. The most fundamental commitment of dialectical materialism is the view that a material world exists independently of the mind prior to human consciousness. Compare Heidegger’s view of Newton’s laws to this statement from Lenin in Materialism and Empirio-Criticism:

Yesterday we did not know that coal tar contained alizarin. Today we learned that it does. The question is, did coal tar contain alizarin yesterday? Of course it did. To doubt it would be to make a mockery of modern science… Things exist independently of our consciousness, independently of our perceptions, outside of us, for it is beyond doubt that alizarin existed in coal tar yesterday and it is equally beyond doubt that yesterday we knew nothing of the existence of this alizarin and received no sensations from it.17

On the question of whether there are “eternal truths,” Engels states quite clearly in Anti-Dühring that “certainly there are,” writing:

If it gives anyone any pleasure to use mighty words for such simple things, it can be asserted that certain results obtained by these [physical] sciences are eternal truths, final and ultimate truths; for which reason these sciences are known as the exact sciences. But very far from all their results have this validity.18

Engels is quite careful to acknowledge that even the exact sciences are “swamped by hypotheses as if attacked by a swarm of bees,” yet such hypotheses and abstractions are necessary for scientific progress. Many scientific theories are not valid for every single thing in reality, but indeed have a limited or restricted validity. Einstein’s theory of relativity, for example, cannot explain quantum mechanics, yet our iPhones can still accurately pinpoint our locations by communicating with satellites, a feat that would be impossible without Einstein’s equations. The restricted validity of Einstein’s theories does not falsify the results of our GPS.

Against these common sense positions, Heidegger engages in what Lukács rightly calls a “terminological camouflaging of subjective idealism.”19 Heidegger claims to be talking about being and ontology, yet he actually is talking about the phenomenon or meaning of being. He thus ends up in a position that is more subjectivistic than the idealisms of Husserl or Kant. Heidegger says he is not a subjectivist because he avoids using the language of “consciousness” or “mind,” yet Heidegger simply reduces all objectivity to human existenceand history. Scientific objectivity, truth, and being itself only appear within the human sphere, and if human beings cease to exist (and if there are no “Daseins” on other planets), truth no longer exists.

Heideggerian Thought Today

Recently, some contemporary decolonial theorists have unquestioningly adopted this Heideggerian philosophical framework. Like Heidegger, these thinkers reduce being to our understanding of being. Decolonial theorists like Mignolo and Maldonado-Torres, for example, talk about the “coloniality of being,” yet by “being” they do not mean the actual theft of material resources or the exploitation of labor by the colonizers, but the structure of meaning or appearances. Of course, Marxists should not deny that certain philosophical ideas and epistemological frameworks are indeed influenced by colonialism. For example, Heidegger’s philosophy was influenced by Nazism, a racist and colonial ideology, so if the “coloniality of being” is anywhere, it is in Heidegger’s Eurocentric history of being.20 These decolonial theorists, however, take Heidegger’s framework of the history of being yet rewrite this history so that the meaning of being is somehow determined by colonialism. Everything that takes place after colonialism allegedly corresponds to the “coloniality of being.” When Descartes says: “I think, therefore I am,” this is based in the “I conquer, therefore I am,” a skepticism about the humanity of indigenous peoples and a desire to assert one’s own European identity.21 Since these theorists do not distinguish between being and the understanding of being, they tend to see the “coloniality of being” everywhere (except perhaps in the real material relations of neocolonialism). As Maldonado-Torres writes: “as modern subjects, we breathe [sic] colonialism all the time and everyday.”22 For these decolonial theorists, “coloniality survives colonialism,” meaning the legacy of colonialism primarily exists in certain “colonial” modes of knowing that determine the meaning of being, not in the real continuation of colonial relations of exploitation through neo-colonialism or imperialism (nor the literal colonialism currently taking place in Palestine, Hawaii, Puerto Rico, and elsewhere). The task becomes criticizing ideas for their “coloniality” and trying to produce alternative “decolonized” ways of thinking rooted in non-European epistemologies. The ontological becomes epistemological. The real struggle becomes a war of ideas.

Heidegger frames his history of being in an idealist fashion. He has no understanding of the real driving forces of history. For Heidegger, history is just different paradigms of being, new ways of understanding the meaning of being, different interpretations of the meaning of human existence and the things around us. In each historical epoch, the meaning of being is metaphysically determined, the ontological difference disappears behind an ontotheological metaphysic, and being no longer reveals beings in any other way. If history is determined by various representations of being, then the driving forces of history are ideas and interpretations, not the real events occurring in society and nature. Against Heidegger and those who follow him on his quest for being, I would simply say that after a decade of searching for the meaning of being, I found the answer in Hegel’s Logic. “Being itself” is an abstraction, devoid of all content. The meaning of being is nothing.23

 

https://mronline.org/2024/03/29/why-the-left-should-reject-heideggers-thought-part-1-the-question-of-being/

 

GUS: I NEVER KNEW HEIDEGGER HAD EXISTED... 

 

READ FROM TOP

 

FREE JULIAN ASSANGE NOW....